10/04/2011
today, the issue of
class formation
among historians, class
formation refers to the structural process by which a class emerges.
this isn't our concern, today—not the emergence of social
structures, but rather the formation of class political capacity. its
organization as a coherent actor.
you would think that
nothing is more important in Marxist theory than the question of
class formation. but, as a theoretical issue, the issue has been
sidelined; it's been central to political debates, without being
heavily theorized.
the questions were
always dealt with concretely, in context, but not cashed out in
abstract terms.
the Second
International is full of this kind of stuff; deserves to be mined for
insights. we don't have 'data', because—unlike then—we're nowhere
near power.
this issue is dealt
with, theoretically, by the 'New Left'. it didn't last long,
unfortunately—partly because the New Left gives up on class, but
also because not many of the individuals on the New Left were
embedded in organizing and struggle.
central to Offie and
Wiezenthal's argument is the claim that there's a systematic link
between class structure and class formation—the structure sets the
constraints on actors' ability to organize around their interests.
importantly, this is a story of differential constraints.
the argument is made at
a very high level of abstraction. a strength of the theory, insofar
as this suggests that certain barriers to organizing are intrinsic to
the structure of capitalism. descending levels of abstraction,
introducing race and whatnot, will not erase these basic barriers.
why do classes
organize, at all?
indeed, Offie and
Wiezenthal argue that only one of capitalism's two constitutive
classes has to organize. capitalists do not need organization, in
order to advance their interests. the very fact of capitalist
reproduction ensures that capitalists keep the upper hand.
workers, however,
cannot advance their interests except through organizing. if
left to themselves, workers are at the mercy of capitalists.
thus, for capitalists,
political organization merely amplifies an already-existing
structural advantage. in effect, capitalists can devote their
energies to breaking workers' organization.
it is workers that have
to expend their resources on forming organizations.
thus, first, the
facts about the class structure explain why some actors have to
organize themselves.
the second part
of the argument concerns the question of what makes workers
successful. for the New Left, the failure of workers to organize was
an indictment of Marxism, exhibiting the irrelevance of 'class' to
social structure, etc. hence the flight from class.
the power of Offie and
Wiezenthal's analysis is that it undermines this, at its root. they
suggest that the 'infinite divisions' argument presupposes a world of
interest groups, not of classes. this is pluralism—politics comes
out of the contingent clash of interest groups.
(agency is an 'elixir'
that dissolves all social structures)
Offie and Wiezenthal
reject this. centrally, their argument is that the structure of
capitalism doesn't just distribute interests differentially, but it
also distributes capacities unevenly. the organization of workers is
continually undercut by the structure of capitalism.
the inability of
workers to organize is not a refutation of Marx's theory, but a
confirmation.
why? what are the
mechanisms?
when capitalists and
workers undertake their exchange on the market, they do this as class
actors.
when they organize
themselves, inhibiting mechanisms appear.
the first
weakness, for workers, is the uniqueness of labour-power as a
commodity. capital is a fluid, malleable substance, that can be
detached, split up, and also amalgamate. it's never attached to a
person. workers cannot become bigger and bigger workers,
individually—they can only become bigger associations of workers.
this is associating (for workers), versus merging (for capital).
critically, this fact
has differential consequences. when you try and form bigger and
bigger associations, workers will be more effective—BUT, you have
to combat the problem of its constitutive heterogeneity.
three problems
emerge.
first, the
problem of trade-offs—different workers will attach different
valuations to different issues/demands, in a campaign. associations
will have to prioritize demands. the issue of interest aggregation.
second,
different workers have different bargaining positions. for some
workers (the least-skilled, the poorest, etc.), collective
organization is everything; for others, though, there are workers for
whom individual survival strategies are practicable. [here we've
descended a level of abstraction, of course].
now, the task for
organizers is to convince some workers to redefine their interests.
third, for every
worker who is employed by a capitalist, he cannot avoid the problem
that he can't escape his employers' interest. workers depend on the
employer for their livelihood. the viability of the employers firm
has to be one of the constraints that the workers take on board, when
aggregating their interests. this is not true for the employer.
this is the structural
root of business unionism (the philosophy that says labor and capital
are partners in an enterprise). it's rational, all else being equal.
this is where Bob Fitch goes wrong.
fourth, all
union organizing takes place in the context of managerial power. once
you see reason for some employees to resist association, employers
have the power to repress all organizing efforts. William Z. Foster's
essays, on this score.
these are all the
dilemmas that enter into the formation of organizations.
the next dilemma, Offie
and Wiezenthal argue, regards organizational sustainability. unions
need to be large, but largeness begins to entail trade-offs that lead
to bureaucratization. unions, also, have to exert control over their
membership—they have, after all, promised their employers labour
peace. they have to squelch the internal life of the union. as this
happens, the union is less likely to generate feelings of solidarity,
and thus less likely to induce members to act. workers are more
likely to become free-riders, seeking to minimize the costs they will
bear in the course of collective action.
thus, if despite
capitalism's continual generation of antagonisms, it remains stable,
this is why: it is exceedingly difficult for workers to effectuate
the strategies required to defend their interests. capitalist
dominance is built into the structure of capitalism.
this is the cruel irony
of capitalism—the agents that most need organization are those who
are least able to effectuate it.
- - - - - -
No comments:
Post a Comment