09/28/2011
class structures
generate rules of reproduction.
in capitalism,
capitalists have to find and utilize labour to produce commodities
that they have to sell, competitively, on the market.
workers have to find
employment, and submit to the authority of capitalists for a given
period of time (to some extent).
this process pits these
two classes against one another, generating antagonisms.
'labor and monopoly
capital' virtually started labour process theory. this was an
enormously influential book.
the
labour process is common to all social structures. defined as the way
in which workers and means of production are put together, to produce
goods. has a validity across MoP. in class societies, this can
always be divided into necessary labour, and surplus labour.
but
there's something distinctive about capitalism. prior to capitalism,
the weight of the surplus component is limited by the necessary
component; the surplus component is a residual. this is because of
(1) weakly developed productive forces; (2) in all pre-capitalist
societies, the guiding motif is use-values—what is produced is
geared to 'needs' of producing classes [is this the best way to
cash this out? shouldn't it, instead, be in terms of what producers
can be forced to do? because there are always imperatives to increase
surplus]
in
other words, the surplus is not driven by the immediate needs of the
surplus class to produce a profit—they will need military
expenditure, and they will need things to consume—but neither of
these imperatives place a significant weight on the direct producers.
[a 'weak compulsion' argument (which is different from Brenner's
arguments about feudalism, which is more of an 'incapacity to compel'
argument]
in
capitalism, all the emphasis is on the valorization process—the
labour process is now subjugated to it.
these
carries two consequences
- now, the capitalist is not merely trying to extract surplus labour—but he's trying to extract it to the maximum level possible.
- moreover, the capitalist wants to extract surplus at levels of efficiency that enable him to compete effectively.
in
other words—capitalists try to get workers to work as long and as
hard as possible in order to successfully compete.
once
the capitalist takes control of the labour process and tries to
extract labour at a competitive level, it generates a conflict. the
drive to rationalize the labour process invariably induces a
response, to resist.
this
is the crucial precondition for the resort to managerial authority.
managers exist for one basic reason—workers don't do what
capitalists want them to do, absent being told to. workers are not
fundamentally driven by the competitive logic that drives
capitalists.
managers
have to find ways to reduce workers' resistance to the change of the
labour process and technological change—and the way they do this is
by removing their control over work. one example of this, of course,
is through the breaking of the monopoly of knowledge that workers
have over their work (vivek arguing that breaking monopoly of
knowledge is an instance of a more generic drive to seize control;
otherwise unduly highlighted in the literature, instead of this more
important fact of seizing control).
this is the source of
'de-skilling'. in some ways, this isn't the best term—what he
means, more, is the 'breaking down' of tasks, within a workplace. as
tasks are broken down, workers will require less skills, of course.
BUT, this should not be mistaken as a secular tendency towards
de-skilling, at the general level of the economy. Braverman's
argument is cashed out at the level of the job/task, not the level of
the economy.
the issue of
resistance—Braverman is often accused of ignoring resistance of
workers to technical change. (1) this misundertands the object of
Braverman's work—he isn't predicting an inevitable outcome. he's
simply trying to theorize capitalism's drive to break down the labour
process. resistance introduces ineterminacy, OK; (2) moreover,
empirically—the basic fact is that capitalism has won.
the goal of theory is
not to make you feel better about the world. one has to understand
how capitalism works; except in very exceptional circumstances, for
short periods of time, capitalists win. 'if everything was
contingent, we wouldn't need socialism.'
is Foucault like
Braverman? first, Foucault doesn't have a theory—no explanation of
where a 'disciplinary' drive comes from. for Braverman, its Capital;
for Foucault, doesn't exist. second, Braverman's
normative/descriptive framework has some understanding of what human
flourishing is, what human interests are. this is what it means for
this to be a 'degradation' of work. Foucault's entire project is
driven by the denial of human interests.
in Foucault's ontology,
the human agent is the consequence of power structures. whereas for
Braverman, we are confronting humans, with interests, stuck in power
structures.
re: racism, two
distinct claims: (1) capitalism everywhere generates racism; (2)
race/racism is integral to capitalism, when describing it at the
highest level of abstraction.
it doesn't follow that
you can abstract away from gendered/racialized identities to
understand the real world. although, of course, we are staking
importance in our abstract model—we think capitalism's drives exist
everywhere and importantly independent of any given culture. we think
it explains the world—re: race, we think it explains the terrain
that generates racism (in other words, we don't give it theoretical
priority—its not the 'base'), and on which we will have to fight
our anti-racist struggle.
see Jane Humphries RRPE
on women's oppression
abstract labour is not
a different kind of labour, from concrete labour—labour is always
and everywhere concrete.
No comments:
Post a Comment