(171): against liberal vision, we assert that the 'freedoms' of the bourgeois world actually produce and reproduce "factual inequality on the largest scale." [this mode of proceeding is unclear, to me--why not simply term the liberal commitment incomplete, since it was never meant to apply across the board? or as negative vs. positive commitment?]
(172): sociological critique shows that inequality prevails even where we have political and economic equality [but equality in what sense, here? no guilds, full commodification?]. and surely you can have a philosophical critique of bourgeois society? all this is a bit odd.
(173): key--four properties of labor-power:
- cannot be physically separated from its owner
- does not exist because of the expectation of its saleability
- it is of no use-value to its owner (outside of exchange)
- the owner is compelled, therefore, to enter into a wage-contract
(176-194): distinguishing labor and capital on three counts:
- input factors (176-184)--insuperable individuality of labour (178); atomized form of living labour vs. integrated form of 'dead' labor (178); multitude of needs, for labour, vs. just one for capital (179); capital can introduce technical change and lessen its dependence on labor, while labor has no such option (180)--the costs of being unemployed, for labor, are much higher than the costs of not employing labor, for capital; thus:L= three possibilities of resistance (182-183)--(1) individual (lose); (2) collective (lose, because individual interests remain unchanged); (3) collective, interest-changing (now you're talking--have to convince 'relatively powerless' workers that the costs of organization, are low--"redefinition of collective interests").
- internal processes (184-191)--unions need "conscious and coordinated active paritipation of their members" (not individuals, not bureaucracy) (185); danger of size or organization decreasing potential power (due to bureaucratization) (186); bureaucracy/democracy balance (187); unions are forced to represent a 'totality of interests', whereas business associations deal with limited and specific goals (190).
- outputs (191-194)--the State is much kinder to capital, than labor, because it depends on the former (191); the State is dependent on capitalists to a degree that capitalists are not dependent on the State (192) [questionable?].
(194-195): liberal vision rests on 'practical positivism'--an individual's interests are exactly what they say they are (this gives you Carl Schmitt--dictatorships can only have democratic means)
(196-197): claim, here, is that likelihood of interest misrecognition is not evenly distributed amongst the classes.
(198-199): five reasons that it is easy for capitalism to recognize its interests:
- in capitalist society, pursuit of capitalist interests is considered just/normal; this is not the case for workers
- supported by the state apparatus, which depends on capitalists
- has a 'monological' interest, insofar as individual capitalists can pursue their 'true' interests without consulting others (whereas workers require a 'dialogical' process)
- a false notion, for capitalists, will be immediately corrected by the market
- because of bourgeois hegemony, it is more difficult for the workers to shape their interests autonomous from capitalist influence; for the capitalists, of course, bourgeois hegemony is hardly a problem [question is, of course, whether this is what we're trying to explain]
(200): important-- the inherent ambiguity of interest explicit in the workers' position (they are objects and partners in the labor contract, object and subject of exchange)--all ambiguities follow from this basic one:
- between individualistic and collective improvement
- between political and economic interest
- between identity as consumer and identity as producer
- between higher wages and better working conditions/secure employment
- between individual competitiveness and class solidarity
(204): liberal political theory cannot accept the second level of collective action (the 'dialogical'); the 'monological' is encouraged.
(206-207): three theoretical alternatives for unions, then:
- an expansion of the 'dialogical' logic--this requires nothing less than a model of socialist transformation.
- expansion of the 'monological' logic--this is a 'corporatist' formula, presuming imposition from the outside
- the uneasy and temporary coexistence of 'dialogical' and 'monological' logics--this is a result of some internal dynamic, within the working-class organization, and will result--eventually--in decline (though, they will say, this is temporarily rational, nonetheless). it is this they endeavor to make sense of.
- limitations of demands made by unions
- institutionalization of alternative interest representation (works councils, etc)--this dissocioates representation from struggle, they argue.
- statuatory increases of diversity and conflict within unions--in other words, the strategic attempt to bring forward elements that have been coopted
- inversion of means-end, elevation of institutionalized means
- priority given to short-term accomplishments
- emphasis upon quantitative criteria (recruitment) rather than qualitative (formation and expression of collective identities
- small-scale and militant conflict
- here, the dilemma between dialogical and monological forms emerges--it has to recruit and activate members; but it also has to hold these members in check. it will, from here, go to Stage 3 absent mass class struggle outside of itself.
- opportunist resolution--maximizing independence of functionaries, from its base (again, this is rational--it needs to secure success and escape threats to its survival [in what sense is this the case, though?])
- it now loses all capacity to act, due to the separation from its base
- the option of going back to stage I (reversal of institutionalization), or more-or-less decomposing (I think)
No comments:
Post a Comment